Summary
Aristotle suggests that it is human nature to write and appreciate poetry. We
are by nature imitative creatures that learn and excel by imitating others, and
we naturally take delight in works of imitation. As evidence of the claim that
we delight in imitation, he points out that we are fascinated by representations
of dead bodies or disgusting animals even though the things themselves would
repel us. Aristotle suggests that we can also learn by examining representations
and imitations of things and that learning is one of the greatest pleasures
there is. Rhythm and harmony also come naturally to us, so that poetry gradually
evolved out of our improvisations with these media.
As poetry evolved, a sharp division developed between serious writers who would
write about noble characters in lofty hymns and panegyrics, and meaner writers
who would write about ignoble characters in demeaning invectives. Tragedy and
comedy are later developments that are the grandest representation of their
respective traditions: tragedy of the lofty tradition and comedy of the mean
tradition.
Aristotle stops short of saying that tragedy has achieved its complete and
finished form. He lists four innovations in the development from improvised
dithyrambs toward the tragedies of his day. Dithyrambs were sung in honor of
Dionysus, god of wine, by a chorus of around fifty men and boys, often
accompanied by a narrator. Aeschylus is responsible for the
first innovation, reducing the number of the chorus and introducing a second
actor on stage, which made dialogue the central focus of the poem. Second,
Sophocles added a third actor and also introduced background
scenery. Third, tragedy developed an air of seriousness, and the meter changed
from a trochaic rhythm, which is more suitable for dancing, to an iambic rhythm,
which is closer to the natural rhythms of conversational speech. Fourth, tragedy
developed a plurality of episodes, or acts.
Next, Aristotle elaborates on what he means when he says that comedy deals with
people worse than us ourselves, saying that comedy deals with the ridiculous. He
defines the ridiculous as a kind of ugliness that does no harm to anybody else.
Aristotle is able only to give a very sketchy account of the origins of comedy,
because it was not generally treated with the same respect as tragedy and so
there are fewer records of the innovations that led to its present form.
While both tragedy and epic poetry deal with lofty subjects in a grand style of
verse, Aristotle notes three significant differences between the two genres.
First, tragedy is told in a dramatic, rather than narrative, form, and employs
several different kinds of verse while epic poetry employs only one. Second, the
action of a tragedy is usually confined to a single day, and so the tragedy
itself is usually much shorter than an epic poem. Third, while tragedy has all
the elements that are characteristic of epic poetry, it also has some additional
elements that are unique to it alone.
Analysis
Aristotle further elaborates on the value of the mimetic arts with his
assertion that we are naturally imitative creatures who delight in imitation.
Aristotle relates this claim to our ability to learn and reason: we exercise our
reason when seeing something as an imitation of something else. It takes a
certain level of recognition to see a bunch of men dancing and singing in masks
as imitations of characters from ancient myths, to see stylized gestures as
imitations of real action, or to see the emotional intensity generated both by
actors and audience as an imitation of the emotional intensity that would have
been felt if the action on stage were transpiring in real life. Aristotle
defines humans as rational animals, suggesting that our rationality is what
distinguishes us from other creatures. If the ability to recognize an imitation
and understand what it is meant to represent requires reasoning, then we are
delighting in that very faculty that makes us human.
Aristotle's account of the origin of tragedy seems on the whole quite sound. The
sparseness of archaeological and other evidence has long frustrated scholars,
but it seems that Aristotle's suggestion that tragedy evolved from the dithyramb
is as good as any we have. Dionysus is the Greek god of vegetation and wine, and
the dithyrambs in honor of him are thought to have been part of festivals
celebrating the harvest and the changing of the seasons. These songs were thus
part of religious ceremonies, and the speaker that accompanied the large chorus
was probably a priest of some sort. Though initially improvised, these
dithyrambs developed a more rigid structure, and the speaker often engaged in
dialogue with the chorus. Aeschylus is generally credited
with the innovation of adding a second actor, which transformed choral singing
into dialogue, ritual into drama. In short, Aeschylus invented tragedy and is
the first great playwright of the Western tradition.
Near the end of Chapter 5, Aristotle mentions that one of the differences
between tragedy and epic poetry is that the action of a tragedy usually unfolds
in the space of a single day. This is often interpreted as one of the three
"unities" of tragic drama. In fact, the three unities—unity of action
(one single plot with no loose threads), unity of time (action takes place
within a single day), and unity of place (action takes place in a single
location)—were not invented by Aristotle at all. The Italian theorist
Lodovico Castelvetro formalized these unities in 1570. This formalization was
inspired by the Poetics, but it is far more restrictive than anything
Aristotle says. The only unity he insists upon, as we shall see, is the unity of
action. His reference here to the unity of time seems to be a general guideline
and not one that must be followed strictly, and there is even less evidence to
suggest that Aristotle demanded unity of place. The fact is, Aristotle's
formulas were all drawn from Greek tragedy, and these tragedies frequently
violated the unities of time and place.