Suggestions
Use up and down arrows to review and enter to select.Please wait while we process your payment
If you don't see it, please check your spam folder. Sometimes it can end up there.
If you don't see it, please check your spam folder. Sometimes it can end up there.
Please wait while we process your payment
By signing up you agree to our terms and privacy policy.
Don’t have an account? Subscribe now
Create Your Account
Sign up for your FREE 7-day trial
Already have an account? Log in
Your Email
Choose Your Plan
Save over 50% with a SparkNotes PLUS Annual Plan!
Purchasing SparkNotes PLUS for a group?
Get Annual Plans at a discount when you buy 2 or more!
Price
$24.99 $18.74 /subscription + tax
Subtotal $37.48 + tax
Save 25% on 2-49 accounts
Save 30% on 50-99 accounts
Want 100 or more? Contact us for a customized plan.
Your Plan
Payment Details
Payment Summary
SparkNotes Plus
You'll be billed after your free trial ends.
7-Day Free Trial
Not Applicable
Renews June 12, 2023 June 5, 2023
Discounts (applied to next billing)
DUE NOW
US $0.00
SNPLUSROCKS20 | 20% Discount
This is not a valid promo code.
Discount Code (one code per order)
SparkNotes Plus subscription is $4.99/month or $24.99/year as selected above. The free trial period is the first 7 days of your subscription. TO CANCEL YOUR SUBSCRIPTION AND AVOID BEING CHARGED, YOU MUST CANCEL BEFORE THE END OF THE FREE TRIAL PERIOD. You may cancel your subscription on your Subscription and Billing page or contact Customer Support at custserv@bn.com. Your subscription will continue automatically once the free trial period is over. Free trial is available to new customers only.
Choose Your Plan
For the next 7 days, you'll have access to awesome PLUS stuff like AP English test prep, No Fear Shakespeare translations and audio, a note-taking tool, personalized dashboard, & much more!
You’ve successfully purchased a group discount. Your group members can use the joining link below to redeem their group membership. You'll also receive an email with the link.
Members will be prompted to log in or create an account to redeem their group membership.
Thanks for creating a SparkNotes account! Continue to start your free trial.
Please wait while we process your payment
Your PLUS subscription has expired
Please wait while we process your payment
Please wait while we process your payment
Russell's topic in this chapter is knowledge by induction; he addresses its validity and our capacity to understand it. The principle of induction is the cornerstone in Russell's discussion of knowledge of things beyond acquaintance. He has established so far that we are acquainted with our sense-data and our memories of past sense-data (and probably also with ourselves). To extend our understanding beyond the range of immediate experience, we draw inferences. In this way we approach things outside our realm of acquaintance, like physical objects, matter, other people, a past before individual consciousness, things we could not know otherwise. Inferences depend on general principles. In order to draw an inference, it must be known that "some one sort of thing A, is a sign of the existence of some other sort of thing, B." The existence of thunder usually signifies that lightning has come just before. Russell believes that inferential judgments happen every day and, though they cannot be proven to be accurate, provide a useful extension of knowledge beyond our private experience.
Our expectation that the sun will rise tomorrow is an essential case for Russell. Such an expectation is a usual one, one which never seems to come under suspicion or doubt. Now, Russell asks whether or not this belief is a reasonable one. Though there is no simple test, he undertakes to find a source of general belief that would justify our expectation. If asked why we believe that the sun will rise tomorrow, one could openly answer, "Because it has always risen every day." We expect the future based on the past. Or, when asked, one might appeal to laws of motion. Unless something interferes with the orbit of earth, a rotating body, then it will continue the same as it always has. To this, Russell rephrases the initial question: what reason do we have to suppose that a law of motion will be sustained from this day to the next?
We believe in the laws of motion, just as we believe in the rising sun, because to our knowledge, there has never been a break in this repetition, this constancy. However, is this reason enough for our belief? "Do any number of cases of a law being fulfilled in the past afford evidence that it will be fulfilled in the future?" Uncertainty about the expectations by which we live our daily lives, such as the expectation that we will not be poisoned by the bread at our next meal, is an unattractive possibility. Russell tries to show next that it is of the essence to our daily life that our expectations seem probable, not certain. He sets out to find a reason in support of the view that our expectations will probably be fulfilled.
Experience shows that "uniform succession or coexistence has been a cause of our expecting the same succession or coexistence on the next occasion." We associate repeated sensations with a certain outcome by habit. Our instincts cause us to anticipate the sun each morning, and they seem valid. Still, the question as to whether there is "reasonable ground" for following such instincts persists. Should we believe in these patterns that are merely consistent as far as we know? Russell proposes that we instinctually assume "the uniformity of nature." We believe that "everything that has happened or will happen is an instance of some general law to which there are no exceptions." We also find this attitude (and perhaps mimic it) in the province of scientific investigation. Science frequently assumes that "general rules that have exceptions can be replaced by general rules which have no exceptions." Laws of motion and laws of gravitation came to account for balloons and airplanes replacing the old rule, "unsupported bodies in air fall," which failed and counted balloons and airplanes as exceptions. Science isolates uniformities that hold as uniform as far as our experience extends. Yet, the uniformity of nature is an assumption that cannot be proven. It holds for all instances in the past, but there is no way of knowing if it will remain constant in the future. Despite many repetitions, an outcome could change even at the last instance and thus "probability is all we ought to seek."
The most stringent degree of certainty about future expectations that we can secure is that the more often that A signifies the occurrence of B, the more probable it is that the instance will also be the case in the future. We may also hope that if A indicates B very frequently, then we may estimate the frequency tantamount to an almost certainty. Russell formulates these observations into two parts, outlining the principle of induction.
First, when a thing of a certain sort A has been found to be associated with a thing of a certain other sort B and has never been found dissociated from a thing of the sort B, the greater the number of cases in which A and B have been associated, the greater is the probability that they will be associated in a fresh case in which one of them is known to be present. Second, under the same circumstances, a sufficient number of cases of association will make the probability of a fresh association nearly a certainty and will make it approach certainty without limit.
Please wait while we process your payment