Analysis

The "unconceived conceived thing" argument which Berkeley presents in this section is often referred to as the "Master Argument;" it is almost universally recognized today as unreliable. Some commentators, such as the Australian philosopher David Stove, go do far as to say that it is too generous to even analyze this line of thought as if it were a real argument. According to Stove, it is no argument at all: it is just a tautologically true premise (i.e. that we cannot have an object in mind without having it in mind) that in no way implies the very substantive conclusion (i.e. that it is impossible to conceive of an object that is not in mind). Stove may well be right in claiming that any real analysis of the argument is too charitable, but Stove himself also emphasizes how influential this argument has been in the history of philosophy. In his book, The Plato Cult he points out that most of the later idealists, such as Kant, Hegel, Schelling, and the British idealists, use versions of the Master Argument to bolster their immaterialist claims. Given the argument's influence, it does seem worthwhile to pay some attention to the Master Argument, and to try to analyze exactly where Berkeley went wrong in his reasoning.

The most popular diagnosis is that Berkeley failed to distinguish the perceptual act from the perceptual content. When I conceive of an idea that is my perceptual act. However, I can isolate from that act the content of the idea I am perceiving. The content of my idea can still be: unconceived tree. The fact that I am now conceiving that idea has no effect on the content itself. The content of my idea is still (unconceived tree). Berkeley is trying to say that there is an inherent contradiction in saying that there exists some X that is both unconceived and conceived by me, and he is right to say this. However, he is overlooking the fact that what is really happening when I conceive of an unconceived tree is this: I am conceiving that (there exists some X that is unconceived), with the act of conception outside of the proposition, or content of the perception.

The philosopher J. L. Mackie has a somewhat different diagnosis, which seems like it might be equally true. He thinks that Berkeley's mistake is in talking about trying to conceive of a particular tree that is supposed to be unconceived. We obviously cannot do this, but what we can easily do is to suppose that there exists a tree somewhere out there that is unconceived. In other words, we can say: there exists a tree such that it is unconceived (i.e. there exists some X such that it is a tree and it is not conceived); but we cannot say: there exists some X such that I conceive X and X is unconceived. Berkeley confuses these two formulations, and claims that we cannot form the first, when, really, it is only the second that we cannot form.

Both of these readings, at the very least show us how we can avoid accepting Berkeley's conclusion. There is also another, slightly more charitable way to understand what Berkeley was thinking here, and while it does not help to make his argument a sound one, it does make him look a little less confused. On this reading (put forward, for instance, by Kenneth Winkler), the Master Argument depends crucially on what has come before (though Berkeley claims that this argument can stand fully on its own). What Berkeley is saying, according to this reading is that we cannot represent an idea to ourselves as mind-independent. We can only represent an idea by drawing on its sensible qualities, and our only grip on these is how they appear to perceivers. So we can only conjure up an idea of a tree as it would look to perceivers. This is our only way to fill out the content of our idea. This reading significantly changes the tenor of the argument: instead of concluding that we cannot conceive of an unconceived object, Berkeley would only be claiming that we cannot conceive of an object as  unconceived. In addition, accepting this argument would now require us to accept his previous claim that all qualities are mind-dependent. If we do not accept that claim (which, presumably, most of us do not) then we have no basis on which to accept this claim.

Nonetheless, this reading of the argument puts Berkeley in a better light. For one thing, the premises, if true, actually would imply the conclusion: if it were really true that the only way to fill out the content of an idea is with sensible qualities, and, further, that sensible qualities are all mind- dependent, then it would follow that we cannot form an idea of an object, except by forming an idea of how it looks to perceivers. In addition, though the weaker conclusion is not what Berkeley claims he wants, it is actually a far preferable conclusion to the stronger one. If Berkeley had really proved that we cannot conceive of unconceived objects, he would have proved even more than he wanted to prove. Notice that nothing about the argument limits the conclusion to material objects. We could say equally well that it is impossible to conceive of God or other minds unconceived. In other words, the argument in its stronger form proves (or, rather, attempts to prove) that there is absolutely nothing outside our own minds—not God, not other people, nothing. Instead of arguing toward idealism, then, it argues toward solipsism (i.e. the belief that I myself am the only existing thing in the world). Nothing about the weaker version of the argument limits it to material objects either, but in this case the conclusion causes no trouble when applied to things other than material objects. Berkeley would agree that we cannot form an idea of God or other minds except by conjuring up sensible qualities; that is why he tells us later that we cannot, in fact, form a positive idea of either of these.

 

Popular pages: Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous