Suggestions
Use up and down arrows to review and enter to select.Please wait while we process your payment
If you don't see it, please check your spam folder. Sometimes it can end up there.
If you don't see it, please check your spam folder. Sometimes it can end up there.
Please wait while we process your payment
By signing up you agree to our terms and privacy policy.
Don’t have an account? Subscribe now
Create Your Account
Sign up for your FREE 7-day trial
Already have an account? Log in
Your Email
Choose Your Plan
Individual
Group Discount
Save over 50% with a SparkNotes PLUS Annual Plan!
Purchasing SparkNotes PLUS for a group?
Get Annual Plans at a discount when you buy 2 or more!
Price
$24.99 $18.74 /subscription + tax
Subtotal $37.48 + tax
Save 25% on 2-49 accounts
Save 30% on 50-99 accounts
Want 100 or more? Contact us for a customized plan.
Your Plan
Payment Details
Payment Summary
SparkNotes Plus
You'll be billed after your free trial ends.
7-Day Free Trial
Not Applicable
Renews December 15, 2023 December 8, 2023
Discounts (applied to next billing)
DUE NOW
US $0.00
SNPLUSROCKS20 | 20% Discount
This is not a valid promo code.
Discount Code (one code per order)
SparkNotes PLUS Annual Plan - Group Discount
Qty: 00
SparkNotes Plus subscription is $4.99/month or $24.99/year as selected above. The free trial period is the first 7 days of your subscription. TO CANCEL YOUR SUBSCRIPTION AND AVOID BEING CHARGED, YOU MUST CANCEL BEFORE THE END OF THE FREE TRIAL PERIOD. You may cancel your subscription on your Subscription and Billing page or contact Customer Support at custserv@bn.com. Your subscription will continue automatically once the free trial period is over. Free trial is available to new customers only.
Choose Your Plan
For the next 7 days, you'll have access to awesome PLUS stuff like AP English test prep, No Fear Shakespeare translations and audio, a note-taking tool, personalized dashboard, & much more!
You’ve successfully purchased a group discount. Your group members can use the joining link below to redeem their group membership. You'll also receive an email with the link.
Members will be prompted to log in or create an account to redeem their group membership.
Thanks for creating a SparkNotes account! Continue to start your free trial.
Please wait while we process your payment
Your PLUS subscription has expired
Please wait while we process your payment
Please wait while we process your payment
Zarathustra hears a soothsayer predicting a great future emptiness, where we will feel incapable of creating anything new, nor even capable of dying out. This prediction puts Zarathustra into a deep depression, during which he dreams that he is a watchman in a castle full of coffins. Suddenly, a wind comes and bursts the gates open and a coffin bursts open full of laughter. One of Zarathustra's disciples interprets this dream as meaning that Zarathustra will awaken us from our gloom and emptiness with his life and laughter.
Zarathustra complains that he has never yet found a complete human being, only "inverse cripples" who excel in one attribute, but who are weak in everything else. He could not bear the present and the past if he could not look forward to a future of whole human beings that redeem this past. The trouble with the past is that we cannot change it. The will suffers, because, no matter how much change and creation it may effect in the future, it cannot change the past. We come to see this suffering of the will as a kind of punishment, and so see all life as suffering and punishment, and seek to cease trying to will anything in order to escape from this punishment. Zarathustra suggests that this pessimism results from seeing the past as an immovable thing that simply occurred without human influence. If we can come to see the past as something that we willed, we can find redemption from our suffering and punishment.
Zarathustra claims to have three kinds of human prudence. First, he suggests that it is better to be deceived from time to time than always to be on guard for deceivers. Second, he admires vain people, because their efforts to please are entertaining and because they are unaware of their own modesty. Third, he scoffs at the small things that people call "evil," suggesting that greatness is only possible through great evil.
Zarathustra leaves the people once more to strengthen himself in solitude. He knows, but is still unable to speak about, the culmination of his philosophy (which we shall see in Part III is the eternal recurrence).
The chapter "On Redemption" revisits the theme of the will to power. Seeking power over—and freedom from—everything external to it, our will finds itself stumped when it confronts the past. I can act in the present to direct my future, but there is nothing that I can do to change my past. All life thrives on change, and the past is a permanent, immobile reminder of our seeming powerlessness.
Zarathustra gives us two analyses of the will when it is confronted with this impediment. In the first analysis, the will suffers because it is unable to overcome this obstacle. Because the past is an immovable feature of life, we come to see all life as unchangeable suffering. The will cannot touch the past, and it suffers so long as this is the case. The only way to overcome this suffering, according to this first analysis, is to stop the act of willing entirely. Thus, the will is turned against itself in a spiritual equivalent to suicide. In this analysis, Nietzsche is almost certainly thinking primarily of Buddhism. Buddhist meditation is essentially an attempt to extinguish the self, and all the desires and passions fueled by selfishness. The ideal of nirvana is a total extinction of the self that Nietzsche would see as the undesirable self-destruction of the will.
Nietzsche views Buddhism as a retreat from life, but he does not give us enough information about Buddhism to justify his position thoroughly. Nietzsche actually knew a great deal about Buddhism, especially for a 19th-century German, so it is surprising that he gives no notice of the forms of Buddhism that preach a suppression of selfish desires in order to engage more fruitfully with this world. Such a view seems to express a healthier version of Nietzsche's will to power. Nietzsche's view of Buddhism is deeply influenced by Schopenhauer's interpretation, and so we are seeing more of a caricature of Schopenhauer's views. This lack of detail is not unique to Nietzsche's treatment of Buddhism either: when talking about both democracy and Christianity, Nietzsche often simplifies matters somewhat.
The second analysis that Zarathustra gives us is that the will should take responsibility for the past, and thus no longer see it as an obstacle. A person subscribing to this outlook would say, I may no longer be able to affect the past, but my past is the past I created, and so it is a permanent testament to the power of my will.
Nietzsche says that his contemporaries cannot presently take responsibility for their past because they are all what he calls (using an offensive phrase) "inverse cripples." Those who seem great merely exceed in one particular attribute, but they are far from being whole human beings. Someone may be vastly creative in one aspect of his or her life, but then fail entirely to be creative in others. For instance, T.S. Eliot revolutionized poetry and was a creative genius, but he was also apparently an unpleasant person, an anti-Semite, a snob, and he clung to Christianity and other traditions that Nietzsche would have considered contemptible. (Nietzsche himself is impaired by his sexist attitudes.)
All these infirmities of what Nietzsche calls "inverse cripples" imply that people lack the full-bodied individuality and creativity of an overman. As a result, we are not in complete control of our destiny and thus not in complete control of our past. Until we can take full responsibility for ourselves, by gaining complete power over ourselves, we cannot redeem our past by claiming responsibility for it.
The key to the "redemption" that Zarathustra longs for is the idea of the eternal recurrence. This idea will become more and more central in parts three and four, and so we will discuss it more in depth when we get to those parts. For now, we should note the ways in which eternal recurrence has been foreshadowed throughout Part II. For instance, the ghost of Zarathustra in the chapter "On the Great Events" and the dream in "The Soothsayer" chapter both predict a coming revelation. Zarathustra's depression, which is alluded to at the end of the "Dancing Song" and in "The Soothsayer" also suggests that he has not yet found the final key. At the end of Part II, he returns to solitude precisely to discover the eternal recurrence.
Please wait while we process your payment