Suggestions
Use up and down arrows to review and enter to select.Please wait while we process your payment
If you don't see it, please check your spam folder. Sometimes it can end up there.
If you don't see it, please check your spam folder. Sometimes it can end up there.
Please wait while we process your payment
By signing up you agree to our terms and privacy policy.
Don’t have an account? Subscribe now
Create Your Account
Sign up for your FREE 7-day trial
Already have an account? Log in
Your Email
Choose Your Plan
Individual
Group Discount
Save over 50% with a SparkNotes PLUS Annual Plan!
Purchasing SparkNotes PLUS for a group?
Get Annual Plans at a discount when you buy 2 or more!
Price
$24.99 $18.74 /subscription + tax
Subtotal $37.48 + tax
Save 25% on 2-49 accounts
Save 30% on 50-99 accounts
Want 100 or more? Contact us for a customized plan.
Your Plan
Payment Details
Payment Summary
SparkNotes Plus
You'll be billed after your free trial ends.
7-Day Free Trial
Not Applicable
Renews December 6, 2023 November 29, 2023
Discounts (applied to next billing)
DUE NOW
US $0.00
SNPLUSROCKS20 | 20% Discount
This is not a valid promo code.
Discount Code (one code per order)
SparkNotes PLUS Annual Plan - Group Discount
Qty: 00
SparkNotes Plus subscription is $4.99/month or $24.99/year as selected above. The free trial period is the first 7 days of your subscription. TO CANCEL YOUR SUBSCRIPTION AND AVOID BEING CHARGED, YOU MUST CANCEL BEFORE THE END OF THE FREE TRIAL PERIOD. You may cancel your subscription on your Subscription and Billing page or contact Customer Support at custserv@bn.com. Your subscription will continue automatically once the free trial period is over. Free trial is available to new customers only.
Choose Your Plan
For the next 7 days, you'll have access to awesome PLUS stuff like AP English test prep, No Fear Shakespeare translations and audio, a note-taking tool, personalized dashboard, & much more!
You’ve successfully purchased a group discount. Your group members can use the joining link below to redeem their group membership. You'll also receive an email with the link.
Members will be prompted to log in or create an account to redeem their group membership.
Thanks for creating a SparkNotes account! Continue to start your free trial.
Please wait while we process your payment
Your PLUS subscription has expired
Please wait while we process your payment
Please wait while we process your payment
The most important and famous results in Special Relativity are that of time dilation and length contraction. Here we will proceed by deriving time dilation and then deducing length contraction from it. It is important to note that we could do it the other way: that is, by beginning with length contraction.
tA = ![]() |
tB = ![]() ![]() |
![]() ![]() |
All this might seem innocuous enough. So, you might say, take the laser away and what is the problem? But time dilation runs deeper than this. Imagine OA waves to OB every time the laser completes a cycle (up and down). Thus according to OA's clock, he waves every tA seconds. But this is not what OB sees. He too must see OA waving just as the laser completes a cycle, however he has measured a longer time for the cycle, so he sees OA waving at him every tB seconds. The only possible explanation is that time runs slowly for OA; all his actions will appear to OB to be in slow motion. Even if we take the laser away, this does not affect the physics of the situation, and the result must still hold. OA's time appears dilated to OB. This will only be true if OA is stationary next to the laser (that is, with respect to the train); if he is not we run into problems with simultaneity and it would not be true that OB would see the waves coincide with the completion of a cycle.
Unfortunately, the most confusing part is yet to come. What happens if we analyze the situation from
OA's point of view: he sees OB flying past at v in the backwards direction (say OB has a laser
on the ground reflecting from a mirror suspended above the ground at height h). The relativity
principle tells us that the same reasoning must apply and thus that OA observes OB's clock
running slowly (note that γ does not depend on the sign of v). How could this possibly be right?
How can OA's clock be running slower than OB's, but OB's be running slower than OA's?
This at least makes sense from the point of view of the relativity principle: we would expect from the
equivalence of all frames that they should see each other in identical ways. The solution to this mini-paradox
lies in the caveat we put on the above description; namely, that for tB = γtA to hold, OA
must be at rest in her frame. Thus the opposite, tA = γtB, must only hold when OB is at
rest in her frame. This means that tB = γtA holds when events occur in the same place in
OA frame, and tA = γtB holds when events occur in the same place in OB's frame.
When v0âáγ
1 this can never be true in both frames at once, hence only one
of the relations holds true. In the last example described (OB flying backward in OA's frame), the
events (laser fired, laser returns) do not occur at the same place in OA's frame so the first relation we
derived (tB = γtA) fails; tA = γtB is true, however.
We will now proceed to derive length contraction given what we know about time dilation. Once again
observer OA is on a train that is moving with velocity v to the right (with respect to the ground). OA
has measured her carriage to have length lA in her reference frame. There is a laser light on the back
wall of the carriage and a mirror on the front wall, as shown in .
tA = ![]() |
tB = ![]() ![]() ![]() ![]() |
γtA = γ![]() ![]() ![]() ![]() ![]() |
Once again the problem seems to be that is we turn the analysis around and view it from OA's point of view: she
sees OB flying past to the left with speed v. We can put OB in an identical (but motionless) train and apply
the same reasoning (just as we did with time dilation) and conclude that OA measures OB's identical carriage to
be short by a factor γ. Thus each observer measures their own train to be longer than the other's. Who is right? To
resolve this mini-paradox we need to be very specific about what we call 'length.' There is only one meaningful definition of
length: we take object we want to measure and write down the coordinates of its ends simultaneously and take the
difference. What length contraction really means then, is that if OA compares the simultaneous coordinates of his own
train to the simultaneous coordinates of OB's train, the difference between the former is greater than the difference between
the latter. Similarly, if OB writes down the simultaneous coordinates of his own train and OA's, he will find the
difference between his own to be greater. Recall from Section
1 that
observers in
different frames have different notions of simultaneous. Now the 'paradox' doesn't seem so surprising at all; the times
at which OA and OB are writing down their coordinates are completely different. A simultaneous measurement for
OA is not a simultaneous measurement for OB, and so we would expect a disagreement as to the observers concept of
length. When the ends are measured simultaneously in OB's frame lB = , and when events are measured
simultaneously in OA's frame lA =
. No contradiction can arise because the criterion of simultaneity
cannot be met in both frames at once.
Please wait while we process your payment